site banner

Culture War Roundup for the week of January 27, 2025

This weekly roundup thread is intended for all culture war posts. 'Culture war' is vaguely defined, but it basically means controversial issues that fall along set tribal lines. Arguments over culture war issues generate a lot of heat and little light, and few deeply entrenched people ever change their minds. This thread is for voicing opinions and analyzing the state of the discussion while trying to optimize for light over heat.

Optimistically, we think that engaging with people you disagree with is worth your time, and so is being nice! Pessimistically, there are many dynamics that can lead discussions on Culture War topics to become unproductive. There's a human tendency to divide along tribal lines, praising your ingroup and vilifying your outgroup - and if you think you find it easy to criticize your ingroup, then it may be that your outgroup is not who you think it is. Extremists with opposing positions can feed off each other, highlighting each other's worst points to justify their own angry rhetoric, which becomes in turn a new example of bad behavior for the other side to highlight.

We would like to avoid these negative dynamics. Accordingly, we ask that you do not use this thread for waging the Culture War. Examples of waging the Culture War:

  • Shaming.

  • Attempting to 'build consensus' or enforce ideological conformity.

  • Making sweeping generalizations to vilify a group you dislike.

  • Recruiting for a cause.

  • Posting links that could be summarized as 'Boo outgroup!' Basically, if your content is 'Can you believe what Those People did this week?' then you should either refrain from posting, or do some very patient work to contextualize and/or steel-man the relevant viewpoint.

In general, you should argue to understand, not to win. This thread is not territory to be claimed by one group or another; indeed, the aim is to have many different viewpoints represented here. Thus, we also ask that you follow some guidelines:

  • Speak plainly. Avoid sarcasm and mockery. When disagreeing with someone, state your objections explicitly.

  • Be as precise and charitable as you can. Don't paraphrase unflatteringly.

  • Don't imply that someone said something they did not say, even if you think it follows from what they said.

  • Write like everyone is reading and you want them to be included in the discussion.

On an ad hoc basis, the mods will try to compile a list of the best posts/comments from the previous week, posted in Quality Contribution threads and archived at /r/TheThread. You may nominate a comment for this list by clicking on 'report' at the bottom of the post and typing 'Actually a quality contribution' as the report reason.

5
Jump in the discussion.

No email address required.

Say then, my friend : Plato on Democracy and Tyranny

(c) J. Nelson Rushton. January 27, 2025 Note: this is the second post in a series. The first one is here.

The ring of power has a will of its own. It betrayed Isildur, to his death. And some things that should not have been forgotten were lost. History became legend. Legend became myth. And for two and a half thousand years, the ring passed out of all knowledge. Until, when chance came, the ring ensnared a new bearer.
-- Spoken by the elf-queen Galadriel in Lord of the Rings

Some people believe that wokeness emerged from the progressive counterculture of the 1960’s. Some hold that it has its roots in the 1930's with FDR and the New Deal. Others say that the origins of wokeness go back to the Frankfurt School of economics in 1920's Germany. Whatever wokeness is at its core, and whether it is good or bad, I submit that it is in fact older than any of that -- and, indeed, very old. That is the main thesis of this essay.

In The Republic, Book VIII (c. 375 BC), Plato described a faction whose social and political agenda included moral relativism, lax enforcement of criminal laws, multiculturalism, equality of outcomes, and the repudiation of their society’s founding principles and traditional values. Plato called the adherents of this ideology dēmokratikoi andres [democratic men]. Plato wrote that a state ruled by such "democratic men" is on the brink of descending into tyranny. Steps along the path to tyranny, as Plato described it, include sexual liberation and equality, aggressive taxation of the rich, expansion of the welfare state, open borders, forgiveness of debts, suppression of dissenting speech, and the confiscation of weapons owned by private citizens. Today, many with a similar agenda refer to themselves as "progressives". Most of them, I suppose, are unaware that they are "progressing" toward a vision of the world that dates back at least two and a half thousand years.


Philosopher Alfred North Whitehead once wrote, the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato [Whitehead (1929): Process and Reality]. Whitehead was exaggerating, of course -- but at any rate this essay will consist literally of a series of footnotes to Plato. To the extent that there is truth in Whitehead's witticism, the difference between this and any other work in the Western canon is that I am up front about what I am doing.

Overview of The Republic, Book VIII

In The Republic, Book VIII (c. 375 BC), Plato takes the view that the chief distinguishing characteristics of a person is the set of virtues that person honors. He sorts men into five basic categories, according to the virtues they honor most:

  • The aristocratic man honors wisdom and integrity.
  • The timocratic man honors martial valor, skill at arms, and military prowess.
  • The oligarchical man honors wealth, and the virtues that enable a person to acquire wealth, such as industriousness and ambition
  • The democratic man honors nothing in particular -- and therefore indulges his appetites without restraint.
  • The tyrannical man honors, or in this case we might say bows down to, the merciless exercise of power.

Plato wrote that a nation's form of government emerges naturally from the values of its citizens, and in particular from the virtues they honor. In Plato's view, when the people of a society honor a certain virtue, they raise up leaders who exhibit that virtue -- and, conversely, when citizens fail to honor a certain virtue, they raise up leaders in whom that virtue is absent. The virtues present and absent in these leaders in turn determine the general character of the government. Thus, Plato writes that in principle there are five basic forms of government, corresponding to the five basic sorts of citizen (though, in practice, any given state is liable to be a mixture of these pure forms):

Do you know that Governments vary as the dispositions of men vary, and that there must be as many of the one as there are of the other? For we cannot suppose that states are made of oak and rock, and not out of the human natures which are in them.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

The five forms government considered by Plato in The Republic are as follows:

  • The aristokratíā is society ruled by men of exceptional wisdom and integrity, because its citizens most honor and admire those traits. Aristokratíā is usually translated as aristocracy, but Plato's intent is quite different from the modern meaning of that word. Plato holds aristokratíā (qua, rule by the wise) to be the ideal form of government, while he explicitly repudiates aristocracy in the modern sense, viz., the rule of hereditary nobles.
  • Plato defines a timocracy as a state ruled by men with a record of exemplary military service -- because its citizens honor the martial virtues most highly. Plato cites Crete and Sparta as examples.
  • He defines an oligarchy as a state governed, officially as well as unofficially, by the wealthy -- who are elevated to power and prestige by a citizenry who prizes wealth and the virtues that enable one to acquire wealth, such as industriousness, sharp dealing, and ambition.
  • Plato uses the word dēmokratía to mean a state ruled by men of no particular virtue -- who are elevated to positions of power, one way or another, by citizens who do not honor virtue. Dēmokratía is usually rendered into English as democracy, but Plato's concept of dēmokratía differs importantly from the modern understanding of democracy, as will be discussed below.
  • A tyrannía, for Plato, is a state ruled by a dictator who has seized power in a revolution or coup d'etat -- with popular support the majority of the population, who welcome such a dictator over them. Tyrannía is usually translated as tyranny. Note that while the words "tyrant" and "tyranny" have a generally negative connotations today, this was less true of their ancient Greek precursors týrannos and tyrannía. Like the word "Marxism" today, there were apparently some in ancient Greece who had an affinity for tyrannía, and some who had an antipathy for it. Plato was one who had antipathy.

Book VIII of The Republic is presented as a narrative relating an archetypal story of how societies can decay over time -- from the ideal form of government, aristokratíā, to the worst form, tyrannía, and passing through the three intermediate forms along the way. At each stage in the process, the regime-change is affected by a change in the values of the public, in terms of the virtues they honor. In other words, for Plato, politics is downstream of culture.

It is easy to see how politics could be downstream of culture in a modern democracy -- because the voting populace consists of the entire adult population, who confer official authority upon whomever they wish. It is less easy to see how politics would be downstream of culture in, say, a timocracy (military rule) or oligarchy (rule by the wealthy), where one class of people has an exclusive hold on official power. The question is why would the class-in-power willingly abdicate that power, or how could it be wrested from them by others with no official authority? One factor in such a transfer of power could be violent revolution or the threat of it -- but it seems that for Plato, this is not the only factor, or even the chief factor. On the whole, the transfers of power from one class to another in Plato's narrative hinge more on moral suasion and perceived legitimacy than on threats or force. The driving force (or the control variable, so to speak) in Plato's theory of political and societal change is what Thomas Paine called the constitution of the people -- that is, the moral character of society. This stands in contradistinction to Karl Marx's theory of dialectical materialism, in which the driving forces of societal change consists in the material conditions under which people live, including the laws they have written on paper.


Plato's Dēmokratía and the Democratic Man

Foreshadowing the Christian doctrine of the “will of the flesh”, Plato argues that men's hearts are naturally home to unclean carnal passions:

I mean those [passions] which are awake when the reasoning and human and ruling power is asleep; then the wild beast within us, gorged with meat or drink, starts up and having shaken off sleep, goes forth to satisfy his desires; and there is no conceivable folly or crime -- not excepting incest or any other unnatural union, or parricide, or the eating of forbidden food -- which at such a time, when he has parted company with all shame and sense, a man may not be ready to commit.... In all of us, even in good men, there is a lawless wild-beast nature, which peers out in sleep.
-- The Republic, Book IX

He writes that while all men have these beastly desires, they are restrained, more in some people and less than others, by law (nomos) and reason (logos):

Certain of the unnecessary pleasures and appetites I conceive to be unlawful; every one appears to have them, but in some persons they are controlled by the laws and by reason.
--The Republic, Book IX

When a society is in decline toward disregard of virtue, it will be a mixture of those who have some regard for virtue left (in particular, "oligarchical" virtues such as industriousness and temperance), and those who have little or none. However, the less virtuous citizens may gradually corrupt the more virtuous and recruit them into their ranks. This recruitment proceeds by Orwellian manipulation of language -- by calling good things evil and evil things good -- and has a religious character, as if the target is being indoctrinated into a cult:

There is a battle and they [a man's less virtuous associates] gain the day, and then modesty, which they call silliness, is ignominiously thrust into exile by them, and temperance, which they nickname unmanliness, is trampled in the mire and cast forth; they persuade men that moderation and orderly expenditure are vulgarity and meanness, and so, by the help of a rabble of evil appetites, they drive them [the man's virtues] beyond the border.

And when they have emptied and swept clean the soul of him who is now in their power and who is being initiated by them in great mysteries, the next thing is to bring back to their house insolence and anarchy and waste and impudence in bright array having garlands on their heads, and a great company with them, hymning their praises and calling them by sweet names; insolence they term breeding, and anarchy liberty, and waste magnificence, and impudence courage. And so the young man passes out of his original nature, which was trained in the school of necessity, into the freedom and libertinism of useless and unnecessary pleasures.
-- The Republic, VIII

Through this process, the recruit is finally transformed into a full blown dimokratikos anēr [Greek: democratic man], who no longer distinguish between clean and unclean desires:

If any one says to him that some pleasures are the satisfactions of good and noble desires, and others of evil desires, and that he ought to use and honour some and chastise and master the others -- whenever this is repeated to him he shakes his head and says that they are all alike, and that one is as good as another... Let him then be set over against democracy; he may truly be called the democratic man.
-- The Republic, VIII

Plato writes that as more and more men within a society are corrupted, the entire society is transformed toward a state of dēmokratía, or virtueless society. Dēmokratía is a challenging word to translate. It is usually rendered as democracy, and its meaning is something like democracy (in the modern sense) in that it entails relatively broad and equal participation in government. In Plato's narrative, however, dēmokratía entails much more: a thoroughgoing ethos of equity, in which people regarded, not only having equal rights of life, liberty and property, but also as being of equal ability, uprightness, and achievement -- regardless of their actual respective degrees of ability, uprightness, or achievement.

According to Plato, the virtueless society has a freewheeling spirit of moral relativism -- and, in that spirit, discards the principles of its national constitution.

See too, I said, the forgiving spirit of democracy, and the 'don't care' about trifles, and the disregard which she shows of all the fine principles which we solemnly laid down at the foundation of the city... how grandly does she trample all these fine notions of ours under her feet.
-- The Republic, Book VII

Its public officials are often selected on the basis of their professed loyalty, rather than ability or integrity,

...never giving a thought to the pursuits which make a statesman, and promoting to honour any one who professes to be the people's friend.
-- The Republic, Book VII

or, in some cases, at random by the drawing of lots, presumably on the grounds that "all men are equal" (Strange as this practice may seem to us today, this was indeed the policy of some Greek city-states in and around the time of Plato):

This is the form of government in which the magistrates are commonly elected by lot.
-- The Republic, Book VII

The society that has ceased to honor virtue repudiates meritocracy:

These and other kindred characteristics are proper to democracy, which is a charming form of government, full of variety and disorder, and dispensing a sort of equality to equals and unequals alike.
-- -- The Republic, Book VII

Since all ways of being are held in equal esteem, the people of the dēmokratía are diverse in their norms and values — one might say “multicultural”:

And just as women and children think a variety of colours to be of all things most charming, so there are many men to whom this State, which is spangled with the manners and characters of mankind, will appear to be the fairest of States.
--The Republic, Book VII

Thus, the society loses its sense of shared national identity and social cohesion:

And there being no necessity, I said, for you to govern in this State, even if you have the capacity, or to be governed, unless you like, or go to war when the rest go to war, or to be at peace when others are at peace, unless you are so dispose.
--The Republic, Book VII

In addition to discarding its traditional principles and values, the dēmokratía neglects enforcement of the law, allowing criminals to freely roam the streets:

Have you not observed how, in a democracy, many persons, although they have been sentenced to death or exile, just stay where they are and walk about the world?
--The Republic, Book VII

In summary, the agenda of Plato's democratic men includes moral relativism, leniency in criminal justice, multiculturalism, equality of outcomes, and a loosening of their society's founding principles and traditional values. Sound Familiar?


Plato's Narrative of the Descent into Tyranny

Say then, my friend, in what manner does tyranny arise? -- that it has a democratic origin is evident. [Plato: The Republic, VIII]

Plato held that a society ruled by "democratic men" -- that is, men who neglect to honor virtue, or to distinguish between clean and unclean desires -- is in danger of degenerating into tyranny. The descent into tyranny is driven by a collection of people Plato calls drones, defined generally as those who do no useful work. The name "drone" is taken from the entomological term for male bees and ants -- who, even in Plato's time, were known to live off of the work of others in their hive, contributing nothing except to reproduce themselves.

Plato's "drones" are a rather curious coalition. He writes that there are two broad sorts: drone followers and drone leaders, which he metaphorically refers to as crawling drones and flying drones. The crawling drones, or drone followers, consist of career criminals and the non-working poor. The flying drones, or drone leaders, are elected officials and government bureaucrats who garner power by catering to the constituency formed by the crawling drones.

May we not say that this is the drone in the house who is like the drone in the honeycomb, and that the one is the plague of the city as the other is of the hive? ...And God has made the flying drones [drone leaders], all without stings, whereas of the walking drones he has made some without stings. but others have dreadful stings; of the stingless class are those who in their old age end as paupers; of the stingers come all the criminal class, as they are termed.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

The descent into tyranny begins the decline of patriarchy within the home.

I mean that the father grows accustomed to descend to the level of his sons and to fear them, and the son is on a level with his father, he having no respect or reverence for either of his parents; and this is his freedom.
--The Republic, Book VIII

Foreigners and resident aliens are treated like citizens:

metic [resident alien] is equal with the citizen and the citizen with the metic, and the stranger is quite as good as either.
--The Republic, Book VIII

Children grow entitled and arrogant, and adults cater to them for fear of being labelled as authoritarians. Everyone wants to be the "cool parent" or the "cool teacher".

In such a state of society the master fears and flatters his students, and the students despise their masters and tutors; young and old are all alike; and the young man is on a level with the old, and is ready to compete with him in word or deed; and old men condescend to the young and are full of pleasantry and gaiety; they are loth to be thought morose and authoritative, and therefore they adopt the manners of the young.

-- The Republic, Book VIII

The decaying society embraces a spirit of sexual liberation and sexual equality.

Nor must I forget to tell [in a democracy] of the liberty and equality of the two sexes in relation to each other. Strange as this practice may seem to us today, this was indeed the policy of some Greek city-states in and around the time of Plato.

-- The Republic, Book VIII

Plato wrote that as the drones grow more numerous, the more ambitious drones begin to occupy positions of power and influence. Meanwhile, their less capable constituents form mobs to shout down speakers and suppress the political speech of those who disagree with them:

In a democracy, they [drones] are almost the entire ruling power, and while the keener sort speak and act, the rest keep buzzing about the bema [public speech platform] and do not suffer a word to be said on the other side; hence in democracies almost everything is managed by the drones.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

There are some members of society who have retained the virtues of the previous generation, such as diligence and temperance. Theses people naturally prosper, but the drones elect leaders who confiscate their wealth and redistribute it:

*Then there is another class which is always being severed from the mass...They are the orderly class, which in a nation of traders sure to be the richest. They are the most squeezable persons and yield the largest amount of honey to the drones... And this is called the wealthy class, and the drones feed upon them... *

And do they not share? Do not their leaders deprive the rich of their estates and distribute them among the people?
-- The Republic, Book VIII

The drones use bureaucratic and criminal indictments to harass and immobilize their political opponents:

Then come impeachments and judgments and trials of one another... The people have always some champion whom they set over them and nurse into greatness.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

The redistribution of wealth continues, including the cancellation of debts:

At first, in the early days of his power, he is full of smiles, and he salutes every one whom he meets, ... liberating debtors, and distributing land to the people and his followers, and wanting to be so kind and good to every one!
-- The Republic, Book VIII

The drones elect a leader who drums up national emergencies as a pretext for expanding the power of government. In Plato’s narrative, the emergency is a war — but a war on poverty, or a war on drugs, or a global pandemic would also do the trick.

He [the tyrant elected by the drones] is always stirring up some war or other, in order that the people may require a leader.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

To enlarge his constituency, the drone-leaders open the borders and encourage the immigration of more drones from foreign countries:

And who are the devoted band, and where will he procure them? They will flock to him, he said, of their own accord, if lie pays them. By the dog! I said, here are more drones, of every sort and from every land.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

In the last stages of social and political decay, corruption spirals out of control. Having plundered the wealth of the upper classes, the tyrant begins to confiscate the property of the working class and underclass that elected him, but now they cannot remove him from power. Plato likens the tyrant to a son who steals from the father who has raised him:

In so far as the fortunes of attainted [accused] persons may suffice, he will be able to diminish the taxes which he would otherwise have to impose upon the people. And when these fail? ... then he and his boon companions, whether male or female, will be maintained out of his father's estate.... By heaven, he said, then the parent will discover what a monster he has been fostering in his bosom; and, when he wants to drive him out, he will find that he is weak and his son strong.
-- The Republic, Book VIII

Finally, the tyrant turns violently on its own citizens, drones and all, after depriving them of the right to bear arms:

Glaucon: Why, you do not mean to say that the tyrant will use violence? What! beat his father if he opposes him?
Socrates: Yes, he will, having first disarmed him. Then he is a parricide, and a cruel guardian of an aged parent; and this is real tyranny, about which there can be no longer a mistake
.
--The Republic, Book VIII


Conclusion

It may be worth mentioning how I came to be acquainted with Plato's account of dēmokratía and the descent into tyranny. I first learned of it in listening to a lecture by Hillsdale College historian Paul Rahe. The lecture was on Plato's Republic for its own sake; Rahe did not make any analogy between Plato's narrative and current day politics, and am not sure whether he intended to. Nevertheless, the analogy was clear to me, and I found it so uncanny that I was incredulous. To be frank, I was pretty sure that Rahe was cherry picking passages from a long text to make it look as though Plato was writing about contemporary politics. So, I read Plato's Republic for myself. In doing so, I found that, contrary to my expectations, Rahe was simply summarizing a section of Book VIII -- and that, if anything, he had undersold the similarity between Plato's "democratic man" and the modern left. I would not insist that you take my word for that, and I do not even believe it would be rational to take my word for it on the basis of the snippets quoted in this essay (for all you know, if you haven't read the text, I am doing what I suspected Rahe of doing). Thus, I invite the reader to examine the relevant sections of Plato's Republic for themselves. The entirety of Book VIII can be read in about an hour, or in two hours for a slow reader like me.

When he spoke of tyranny, Plato was speaking from experience, both personal and collective. At the time he wrote The Republic around 375 BC, Plato's home city of Athens had suffered through four different tyrannical regimes over a two-hundred year period -- including the reign of the so-called "Thirty Tyrants", which Plato himself lived though as a young man, and during which approximately five percent of the population of Athens was murdered by its own government. Summarizing the history of the era, Alexander Hamilton would later write,

It is impossible to read the history of the petty Republics of Greece and Italy, without feeling sensations of horror and disgust at the distractions with which they were continually agitated, and at the rapid succession of revolutions by which they were kept in a state of perpetual vibration between the extremes of tyranny and anarchy. [Hamilton: Federalist #9]

So in The Republic, Plato was not speculating about something distant from his experience. On the contrary, like the "Ghost of Christmases Yet to Come" in Dickens's Christmas Carol, Plato had been where we might be going, and hoped to warn us so that we would be less likely to go there. Plato clearly has a low opinion of the "democratic men" of his own time, and was probably on the other side from them of whatever political aisle ran through Athens at the time. Maybe they were right and he was wrong. But right or wrong, this faction must have existed, more or less as Plato describes them. If Plato made them up out of thin air, then he was not only a philosopher, but a prophet.

If you haven't, I bet you'd be interested in learning about the state of Athenian democracy—Thucydides is pretty good, especially the Landmark edition.

I'm not sure to what extent I buy that the word democracy is different. Sure, it's different from what we call democracy now, in that we usually mean by that an often large representative republic, where we elect or appoint people to various functions, and they do the actual ruling, but their getting there is in some way dependent on popular appointing. Athenian democracy was far more direct: they had deliberative assemblies that were, if I remember correctly, open to all male citizens (note: citizen≠resident). Their trials were also before enormous juries, with hundreds of people. And this is all in a relatively small city-state. But I would think fundamentally, it mostly just has in view the form of government it has, in which there is (largely direct) popular rule, and the other tendencies you describe are just a result of the usual popular tendencies in such a setting. But yes, I agree that we find many of the same tendencies among people today, and a portion of this probably is downstream from our form of regime.

The setting of the Republic, as with the Platonic dialogues in general, is during the Peloponnesian war against Sparta, which Athens eventually lost. They were briefly ruled oligarchically, due to the Spartans, then democracy was restored, before they were conquered by Philip of Macedon, Alexander's father. During the Peloponnesian war, in most greek cities there were differing factions who sought democratic and oligarchic rule, promoted by the Athenians and Spartans respectively.

If I remember correctly, Socrates describes democracies as making philosophy more possible than most of the other regimes.

One other note: drawing of lots isn't all that crazy! We use random chance, to an extent, in our own jury process. Drawing lots has the downside of not letting you choose the most qualified people, and the upside of avoiding any negative effects from what sorts of people would seek out the position.

They [Athens] were briefly ruled oligarchically, due to the Spartans,

This glosses over some things that are worth mentioning, don't you think?

Well, yes.